Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 75-6):
The distinction between internal and external purview also helps us understand the interpersonal dynamics of proposals. Taking (41) as an example, adapted from a different conversation between Kristy and her mum while they are cooking together, there is a question as to who has purview. Is it the one who commands the action (in this case Kristy, who is the A2/secondary actor in Berry’s terms)? Or is it the one who does the action (in this case her mother – the A1/primary actor in Berry’s terms)?(41) Kristy: Put honey in and milkMother: (PUTS HONEY AND MILK IN)For action changes that involve proposals like this, the answer is in fact both. Looking at purview externally, in terms of control over the action, it is the person who does the action that has purview (the mother here as primary actor). But internally, it is the person who does the commanding (Kristy here as secondary actor) who has control over the exchange and the nature of the action. This can be seen from the fact that one can only render Kristy’s command here internally. That is, Kristy's mother can only support or abort the exchange (Put honey in and milk. – No). By contrast, she can render the action itself externally (PUTS HONEY AND MILK IN – Not like that!). This analysis is illustrated in (42):
ChatGPT Comments:
The central issue here is the collapse of distinct categories: the authors treat commands as asserts, purview as control, and conflate exchange roles with action roles.
In sum, the attempt to stretch purview across both exchange and action leads to theoretical drift. Commands are miscast as asserts, exchange grammar is recoded in redundant terminology, and purview itself becomes an unstable placeholder rather than a principled category.
No comments:
Post a Comment