-
Confusion of “purview” with role functions
-
The authors are mixing “purview” with Berry’s A1/A2 distinction, which concerns who initiates vs who responds in an exchange. Instead of clarifying purview, they are folding it into “control” over either action or exchange.
-
This dilutes purview into two unrelated axes:
-
Externally: purview = who performs the action.
-
Internally: purview = who initiates the exchange.
-
-
The result is a split that makes “purview” a floating label with no stable theoretical anchoring.
-
-
Mischaracterisation of commands as “asserts”
-
In (42), Kristy’s command is analysed internally as an “assert” (+ speaker purview, – listener purview). But in Hallidayan terms, a command is not an assert — it is a proposal: a demand for goods-&-services in exchange structure.
-
By forcing it into the “assert” slot, they erode the distinction between giving information (asserting) and demanding action (commanding).
-
-
Circularity of “support/abort” rendering
-
They claim the mother can only “support or abort” Kristy’s command internally — but that’s just a rewording of the basic exchange grammar (support/contradict for information; comply/refuse for goods-&-services).
-
Their terminology (“abort”) adds no theoretical precision, only a gloss that restates Halliday’s original exchange logic.
-
-
Theoretical drift: exchange structure vs action structure
-
They try to straddle two incompatible framings:
-
Internal purview → exchange control (Berry’s model).
-
External purview → action control (who physically does something).
-
-
But this is not an integrated system — it’s a patchwork that confuses linguistic structure with social action sequences.
-
Negotiating Social Relations: Tenor Resources In English
A Meticulous Review Of Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025)
Wednesday, 3 September 2025
Purview Inflation: Seeing Two Propositions Where There Is Only One
Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 78):
Finally, instances that involve projection, such as (52) from a news report given in Martin and White (2005, p. 112), also establish multiple propositions with the potential for different purview (plus sourcing – see Chapter 4).
Here, the reporter does not tie themselves to whether or not the Church of England’s status is indefensible (airing: – speaker purview; – listener purview), but they do assert the fact that a bishop today described the Church of England’s established status as indefensible (+ speaker purview; – listener purview).
ChatGPT Comments:
The example in (52) is mis-analysed. Structurally, we are dealing with a single clause: an attributive clause with assignment (A bishop today describes X as Y). This clause realises only one proposition. It is not a clause complex, nor does it project a secondary clause.
The authors, however, construe the instance as if it contained two propositions:
-
an “air/proposition” (The Church of England’s established status is indefensible), and
-
an “assert/proposition” (A bishop describes…).
By construing a clause as clause complex, the purview framework doubles the number of propositions where there is only one. This not only misrepresents the grammar but also artificially inflates the analytical complexity. Such inflation obscures rather than clarifies the semiotic organisation of discourse.
The added claim that the reporter withholds commitment to the indefensibility of the status, while asserting that a bishop described it as such, depends entirely on this misidentification. There is no separate “inner” proposition that can be independently assigned purview. What the reporter does is to assert a single relational attribution, not to air one proposition and assert another.
In short, the framework here does not clarify interpersonal stance but fabricates distinctions by misconstruing clause structure. And if purview relies on such misconstruals to generate its analytical categories, then the system itself cannot be trusted to track meaning but only to project its own confusions onto the grammar.
Tuesday, 2 September 2025
Purview Confounded: Duplicating Grammar and Semantics as Context
Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 78):
This opens space for reconsidering examples such as (49) above along the same lines, replayed here as (51). Externally speaking, considered in terms of whether or not mass extinctions were caused by changes in sea level or disruptions in the food chain, the proposition is aired – the may indicates that the author is not tied to whether or not this is the case. A response could render this proposition with something like No, they weren’t – focusing on whether or not this was the cause, rather than any negotiation of whether it could be the cause. On the other hand, the possibility of them being caused this way is asserted (through the use of a declarative without any tagging). One could focus on the could and render the possibility of them being caused by saying something like No, they couldn’t have. Asserting this suggests that rejecting the position along these lines would be more socially risky. But for academic discourse in particular, the play between the two purviews given through NEGOTIATION (the statement) and ENGAGEMENT (through the modality could) allows an author to have their cake and eat it too – to assert something baldly while not tying themselves to its actuality.
ChatGPT Comments:
In this excerpt, Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 78) propose a dual-layered system of purview in which external purview (– speaker; + listener) “airs” a proposition, while internal purview (+ speaker; – listener) simultaneously “asserts” its possibility. The example in (51), concerning mass extinctions, is intended to illustrate how an academic author can assert something baldly without committing to its factual actuality.
From a systemic-functional standpoint, however, this theorising is deeply problematic. The authors relocate what are fundamentally clause-level interpersonal distinctions and engagement up into the realm of context (tenor: purview). Grammar and semantics, language, are treated as independent contextual variables, effectively conflating content and context in a manner that SFL explicitly resists. This move is conceptually confused: the internal/external purview distinction does not describe a separate level of social organisation but merely re-describes the interplay of hedging and assertion already encoded in modality.
Further, the dual purview framing introduces unnecessary complexity without explanatory payoff. By splitting a single clause into “external” and “internal” propositions, the system duplicates semantic distinctions at the level of tenor. The distinction between commitment to actuality and commitment to possibility is culturally and register-specific, and cannot reliably support a generalised system of context. The authors’ discussion of “having their cake and eating it too” highlights this: it is less an insight into social interaction than a re-labelling of standard hedging practices in academic English.
In short, the dual purview model is theoretically confused, duplicative, and inconsistent with SFL’s canonical stratification. External and internal purviews do not constitute a new distinction of context; they are a misapplied reinterpretation of what is already realised grammatically and semantically. The excerpt exemplifies the broader issue with purview: by elevating grammar and semantics into tenor, the authors obscure the very mechanisms they claim to describe.
Monday, 1 September 2025
Duplicating Meaning: Grammatical Metaphor Misread as Context in Purview
Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 77-8):
Heteroglossia often involves instances that in fact put forward two (or more) propositions. This opens space to nuance the purview of each position at the same time. For example, (47) above could alternatively have been written as (50).
In this instance, the proposition realised through the embedded clause the organ screen in the stables was designed by Thomas Chippendale indicates – speaker purview (airing), by virtue of the heteroglossic scoping given by it is possible. That is, the speaker is not committed to the proposition about whether or not the organ screen in the stables was designed by Thomas Chippendale. But the ranking clause it is possible... is baldly asserted; the speaker here is committing themselves to it being possible. In other words there are two propositions being put forward with different purview – whether or not the organ screen was designed by Thomas Chippendale is left open, but the possibility that it could have been designed by him is asserted. The distinction between (50), it is possible that.., and (47), possibly, is what Halliday refers to as explicit objective (it is possible that...) vs implicit objective (possibly) modality (Halliday & Matthiessen, 2014, p. 689). Once again we can interpret this opposition in terms of internal and external purview – the proposition of whether or not the design was by Thomas Chippendale is externally aired, but the assessment of its possibility is internally asserted.
ChatGPT Comments:
In this excerpt, the authors attempt to nuance purview through heteroglossic constructions, using (50) to illustrate how an embedded clause can create distinct internal and external purview readings. While the example is linguistically interesting, the account problematically conflates grammatical metaphor with context. Specifically, the authors treat the heteroglossic scoping of it is possible as a separate instance of purview at the level of tenor (context), when in fact this is a classic case of grammatical metaphor operating within the clause itself. The embedded clause the organ screen in the stables was designed by Thomas Chippendale is not introducing a new contextual variable; it realises a semantic expansion.
By reifying internal vs. external purview in this way, the authors effectively duplicate semantic distinctions at the contextual stratum, violating the SFL principle that context (here, tenor) and semantics (here, modality and engagement) are distinct strata, with the latter realising the former. The example conflates the assessment of possibility (internal assertion) with the aired proposition about the design itself (external), treating each as separate contextual positions rather than as grammatical-semantic realisations that encode stance. In short, the conceptual apparatus of purview risks obscuring the actual grammatical mechanism at play, turning a well-known instance of objective modality into an artefact of context.
This approach exemplifies a broader pattern in the book: reinterpreting lexicogrammatical or semantic phenomena as if they were contextual variables, rather than carefully tracking the stratification from semantics to context. While the internal/external purview distinction is analytically neat, its application here stretches the theoretical framework in ways that are not justified by the data or by canonical SFL theory.
Sunday, 31 August 2025
Purview Meets Engagement: Collapsing Strata in SFL
Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 77):
In addition, purview variables can be realised through choices in engagement. For example, monoglossic statements will typically realise an assertion (+ speaker purview; – listener purview), as in the example we saw above (replayed as (46) below).
(46) Mother: You’ll have a lovely day pet. assert/proposition
In terms of Martin and White’s (2005) model of engagement, heteroglossic expansion resources on the hand will typically realise no speaker purview, in addition to any rendering noted above (Zhang 2020c). Adapting examples from Martin and White (2005, p. 107), heteroglossic entertain resources typically indicate neither speaker nor listener purview, and so air their proposition, as in (47) and (48).
(47) The organ screen in the stables was possibly designed by Thomas Chippendale air/propositionWhen interacting with tagging resources, this – speaker purview option may also combine with + listener purview to pose a proposition, as in the constructed example in (49).
(48) Mass extinctions could have been caused by major changes in sea level or disruptions in the food chain. air/proposition(49) The organ screen in the stables was possibly designed by Thomas Chippendale, d’you reckon? pose/proposition
ChatGPT Comments:
In this excerpt, Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 77) extend the system of purview into the realm of engagement, claiming that certain engagement choices—monoglossic versus heteroglossic statements—can realise speaker and listener purview options. They provide examples of assertions, posing, and airing propositions mapped to engagement resources (e.g., heteroglossic entertain → air).
The problem lies in the conflation of strata. In systemic functional linguistics, engagement is a semantic system realised in the lexicogrammar, and prosodic or paralinguistic features may realise content on the expression plane. Doran, Martin & Zappavigna, however, treat engagement as contextual: a system of tenor (purview). By claiming that heteroglossic expansion resources automatically realise “no speaker purview” or that tagging constructs can create a pose, they are effectively duplicating semantic categories at the level of context, rather than analysing how these semantic resources are realised in text or talk.
This raises a broader concern: the system of purview, when applied in this way, risks collapsing the stratification of language, turning lexicogrammar and semantics into context. While the examples are interesting pedagogically, the theoretical move stretches the SFL model beyond its intended distinction between context (field, tenor, mode) and the lexicogrammatical/semantic systems that realise it. In other words, the approach conflates meaning-in-context with meaning-in-text, which undermines the explanatory clarity that stratified systemic functional theory is designed to provide.
Reviewer Comments:
d’you reckon is not a "tagging resource" since, unlike wasn't it?, it does not reprise the Finite and the Subject of the clause.
Saturday, 30 August 2025
Rebranding Mood and Engagement as Context: A Stratificational Misstep
Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 76-7):
As the examples above suggest, the potential realisations of purview options are diverse – for one thing, purview is very sensitive to phonological and paralinguistic (‘body language’) choices (Halliday & Greaves, 2008; Ngo et al., 2022). For example, like for wh- interrogatives, a distinction between the falling tone 1 and rising tone 2 on a declarative would often distinguish assert from pose.(44) Kristy: //1 I don’t want to go away from you // assert/proposition(45) Mother: //2 you don't want to go to Dee’s?// pose/propositionSimilarly, an open posture, supine hand position and/or decentred facial features would typically lessen speaker purview paralinguistically (what (Ngo et al., 2022, p. 144) calls paralinguistic expansion).
ChatGPT Comments:
In their discussion of tenor, Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 76–7) introduce the system of purview, which they locate explicitly at the level of context. At first glance, this seems like a straightforward extension of systemic modelling into new semiotic terrain. But if we look more closely, the theoretical footing becomes much less secure.
The problem is that the categories instantiated in purview are not distinctive features of context at all. Rather, they are drawn wholesale from systems that have long been established at lower strata:
-
mood at the level of grammar
-
engagement at the level of semantics
In other words, what is presented as a system of context is in fact a duplication of grammar and semantics under a new label.
This move creates several problems:
-
Redundancy. Mood and engagement already provide powerful accounts of how interactional stance is construed and realised. Relabelling these same oppositions as “purview” does no additional theoretical work — it simply duplicates categories already accounted for elsewhere in the stratification.
-
Circularity. If purview is said to be realised by tone, gesture, hand orientation, and so on, we immediately face a problem: mood and engagement are already realised by these same resources. The theory starts chasing its own tail.
-
Stratificational incoherence. In the canonical Hallidayan model, context is a higher-order semiotic stratum, realised by semantics. Its function is to model the situation type, not to repeat semantic or grammatical systems in disguise. By shifting mood and engagement “up” into tenor, context ceases to be an independent plane of abstraction. It collapses into a duplicate description of what is already present in the strata below.
What is at stake here is not just terminological neatness, but the integrity of the architecture itself. If context can be populated by rebranded grammatical and semantic categories, then the delicate explanatory hierarchy of SFL is undermined. Context no longer provides a theory of situation, but becomes an echo chamber of lower-level systems.
That’s the kernel of it: the “purview” system does not open up new explanatory ground at the level of tenor; it merely duplicates existing accounts, blurring the very stratificational distinctions on which SFL depends.
Reviewer Comments:
See Problems With The Authors' Analysis Of Paralinguistic Engagement
Friday, 29 August 2025
The Promise of Nuance, the Cost of Clarity
Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 76):
As examples (39)–(43) illustrate the interplay between internal and external purview allows negotiation of different aspects of semiosis to occur at the same time – the proposition or proposal being put forward and the use of language itself. Aside from some examples associated with engagement below, we will not explore in more detail the distinction between internal and external purview here. Needless to say, this distinction opens the way for highly nuanced tendering in conversation.
Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 76) close their discussion by claiming that the distinction between internal and external purview “allows negotiation of different aspects of semiosis to occur at the same time – the proposition or proposal being put forward and the use of language itself.” They then suggest this opens the way for “highly nuanced tendering in conversation.”
But as the preceding examples show, the price of this nuance is the erosion of the very categories that make exchange structure coherent. By repeatedly redescribing proposals as propositions, or by multiplying roles under a “purview” scheme, their model creates complexity without explanatory gain.
Halliday’s system already accounts for the simultaneity they want to highlight: speech function specifies what is at stake in the exchange (information vs. goods-&-services), while mood systematises the grammatical resources for negotiating it. This dual articulation is the negotiation of “different aspects of semiosis.” There is no gap here that requires “purview” to fill.
In effect, the authors promise “nuanced tendering” but achieve it by muddling categories that were already designed to capture the delicacy of interaction. What looks like theoretical sophistication is in fact redundancy and confusion.
Taken together, examples (39)–(43) reveal a consistent pattern. The authors begin with a familiar, well-differentiated set of categories from the exchange system, but in the attempt to introduce “purview” they steadily blur the lines that keep propositions, proposals, roles, and moves distinct. At each step the analysis promises nuance, but delivers redundancy: what is already accounted for in the interplay of speech function and mood is redescribed in terms that add complexity but subtract clarity. By the time they summarise with the language of “highly nuanced tendering,” what is on offer is not delicacy of analysis but a proliferation of overlapping labels. The effect is less a refinement of systemic-functional description than a displacement of it.
Thursday, 28 August 2025
The Offer Overwritten: When Purview Distorts the Exchange
Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 76):
This allows us to understand in more detail the purview of offers in exchanges (exchanges with Da1^A2^A1 as its structure, in Berry’s terms) – as illustrated by (43) from the same text (leaving aside the repositioning). In this example, Kristy’s mother offers to fill the cup. In doing so, she gives internal purview to Kristy to decide whether the action of filling the cup will happen (internal pose), while giving herself purview over actually doing the cup filling (external assert).
In (43), Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 76) attempt to extend their two-tiered account of purview to offers. The example involves Kristy’s mother offering to fill a cup, with Kristy specifying Nearly up to the top. The analysis assigns internal purview to Kristy (she decides whether the cup will be filled) and external purview to the mother (she performs the filling).
This layering produces the same categorical problems we saw with commands. The mother’s initiating move Do you want the cup full? is analysed as both a proposal and an external assert. Yet once again, an act that is structurally a proposal (a demand/give goods-&-services) is relabelled with a category from the domain of propositions. To call an offer an “assert” is to collapse Halliday’s central distinction between propositions and proposals.
The duplication of roles compounds the confusion. The authors claim Kristy’s mother simultaneously “gives Kristy purview over whether the action will happen” (internal pose) while retaining “purview over actually doing it” (external assert). But this is not an insight into exchange structure; it is a restatement of the obvious: an offer entails both a decision and an action. Kristy must accept or reject, and her mother must carry out the action if accepted. The system of speech function already models this through the pairing of offers with acceptances/refusals. No additional “purview” mechanism is needed.
Even more problematically, Kristy’s response Nearly up to the top is labelled a “support proposition.” But this is no proposition at all: it is a specification within the exchange of goods-&-services, a modulation of the proposal. Calling it a “proposition” misrepresents both the role of Kristy’s utterance and the structure of the exchange.
In short, the analysis overwrites the exchange with an improvised two-level purview scheme that obscures the simplicity and precision of Halliday’s model. The price of introducing “purview” is redundancy, category confusion, and the erosion of the core distinction between propositions and proposals.
Wednesday, 27 August 2025
The Command Miscast: When a Proposal Becomes an Assert
Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 75-6):
The distinction between internal and external purview also helps us understand the interpersonal dynamics of proposals. Taking (41) as an example, adapted from a different conversation between Kristy and her mum while they are cooking together, there is a question as to who has purview. Is it the one who commands the action (in this case Kristy, who is the A2/secondary actor in Berry’s terms)? Or is it the one who does the action (in this case her mother – the A1/primary actor in Berry’s terms)?(41) Kristy: Put honey in and milkMother: (PUTS HONEY AND MILK IN)For action changes that involve proposals like this, the answer is in fact both. Looking at purview externally, in terms of control over the action, it is the person who does the action that has purview (the mother here as primary actor). But internally, it is the person who does the commanding (Kristy here as secondary actor) who has control over the exchange and the nature of the action. This can be seen from the fact that one can only render Kristy’s command here internally. That is, Kristy's mother can only support or abort the exchange (Put honey in and milk. – No). By contrast, she can render the action itself externally (PUTS HONEY AND MILK IN – Not like that!). This analysis is illustrated in (42):
ChatGPT Comments:
The central issue here is the collapse of distinct categories: the authors treat commands as asserts, purview as control, and conflate exchange roles with action roles.
In other words…
Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 75–6) propose that the interpersonal dynamics of proposals can be explained through a dual notion of purview: internal purview as control of the exchange and external purview as control of the action. Their illustration, drawn from a cooking interaction between Kristy and her mother, is set out in (41–42).
The problem begins with their treatment of Kristy’s directive Put honey in and milk. In (42), this is analysed as an internal assert (+ speaker purview; – listener purview). But this classification is a category error. A command is not an assert. Within the system of speech function, commands belong to the order of proposals, not propositions. They are demands for goods-&-services, not offers or statements of information. To recast a command as an “assert” collapses the foundational distinction between giving information and demanding action.
This miscasting is not an isolated slip; it follows from the authors’ attempt to split purview into two incompatible dimensions. On the one hand, purview is defined externally as control over the physical action (the mother has purview because she puts the honey and milk in). On the other hand, purview is defined internally as control over the exchange (Kristy has purview because she initiates the command). The result is a patchwork in which the same phenomenon is described under two different and non-integrated logics: exchange structure (Berry’s A1/A2 roles) and action structure (who does what in practice).
The circularity of this analysis is evident in their claim that Kristy’s mother can only “support or abort” the proposal internally, while she can “render the action externally.” This is simply a paraphrase of the exchange system Halliday already modelled: the addressee can either comply or refuse a command. The substitution of “abort” for “refuse” does not advance the analysis, but it does obscure the elegance of the original model.
In sum, the attempt to stretch purview across both exchange and action leads to theoretical drift. Commands are miscast as asserts, exchange grammar is recoded in redundant terminology, and purview itself becomes an unstable placeholder rather than a principled category.
Tuesday, 26 August 2025
Internal Purview and Tone: Repackaging Mood Without Gain
Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 75):
A further contrast in purview for open propositions is shown in (39), from Halliday (1970: 22), where a wh-interrogative is used with different tones – a falling tone (tone 1) in the first example (39a.) and a rising tone (tone 2) in the second example (39b.).(39) a. //1 where are you going//b. //2 where are you going//As Halliday notes, “the first [39a with a falling tone] is a normal question, neither abrupt nor deferential, while the second is deferential: it is a question accompanied by a request for permission to ask ‘where are you going, may I ask’.” (Halliday 1970: 22). We can understand this by considering again the distinction between internal and external readings of these positions. Looking externally, in terms of the ‘information’ being asked for, both simply pose a question – they have the same purview, namely – speaker: + listener. Viewed internally in terms of their role as speech acts initiating exchanges on the other hand, they differ in their purview. Example (39a.), with a falling tone, does not seek permission in any way to ask the question – internally it can be read as an assert (+internal speaker purview; – internal listener purview). By contrast (39b.), with a rising tone, indicates some tentativeness (Halliday & Matthiessen, 2014, p. 169) – in some sense asking permission to initiate the exchange. This example can be read internally as a pose (– internal speaker purview; + internal listener purview).
Similarly, in the Australian English dialect spoken by the first and third authors of this book, open propositions can be internally shared (+ internal speaker purview; + internal listener purview) by using non-lexical tags such as ay (/æɪ/) on a falling tone (tone 1).(40) But what do we do, ay?This example is still asking the question (externally speaking); but through the tag it is making it clear that this is a question which the interlocutors probably both share.
ChatGPT Comments:
Several points stand out:
1. Redundant re-description of mood and tone
-
The authors use Halliday’s falling/rising tone distinctions to motivate internal purview, but SFL already captures this through Mood + Key + intonation patterns.
-
The “internal vs external” distinction is a semantic overlay on phenomena that are already systematically handled by Mood: falling tone = normal declarative/interrogative force; rising tone = tentative or deferential. Their framework does not add explanatory power — it merely renames these distinctions in terms of ± internal speaker/listener purview.
2. Introduction of “internal purview” adds analytic complexity without gain
-
By splitting each proposition into “internal” vs “external” purview, the authors create a nested system on top of the existing SFL apparatus.
-
This doubling is not justified empirically: there is no demonstration that these “internal” values capture patterns beyond what tone, key, and mood already explain.
3. Conflation of surface markers and systemic categories
-
Tone, lexical tags, and intonation contours are used as evidence of purview categories.
-
But purview is positioned as a systemic feature of context, not a phonetic or prosodic feature. By grounding purview in tone and tags, they blur the line between language and context, which was already a problematic aspect of the earlier discussion.
4. Circular reasoning
-
They argue: rising/falling tone distinguishes internal purview, then show examples with rising/falling tone to demonstrate internal purview.
-
This mirrors the circularity seen in previous critiques: the data are interpreted to fit the framework rather than to test it.
Overall assessment
-
The excerpt exemplifies the recurring problem: the “purview” system often renames or overlays phenomena already described by SFL (Mood, intonation, key) without adding genuine analytic leverage.
-
The introduction of internal/external purview, and the use of sociolectal features like ay, highlights the fragility and non-generalisability of the framework.
Monday, 25 August 2025
Purview Collapsing into Mood: The Misdescription of Wh-Questions
Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 74-5):
The examples above all focused on complete propositions and proposals. For proposition or proposals that are open, often involving wh– questions, the default purview is pose (–speaker purview; + listener purview). We can see this in (37), where Kristy poses a wh-question to her mother.
Though as example (30) above shows, open propositions can have their purview varied – in this case as aired, through I wonder (replayed in (38)).
ChatGPT Comments:
This continues the same issues we’ve seen earlier:
-
Circularity of “default” — The claim that open wh– questions default to pose (– speaker purview; + listener purview) is not an explanation but a tautological restatement of their own invented system. They say “the default is pose” because their grid requires it, not because any descriptive evidence demands it.
-
Category slippage — They oscillate between proposition type (wh– interrogative) and purview value (pose vs air), treating one as if it naturally “defaults” into the other. But they provide no systemic grounding: in SFL, the default mapping between interrogatives and exchange roles is already accounted for in mood structure. Their “default purview” adds nothing except redundancy.
-
Recycling the same example — Example (37) is simply a restaging of Kristy’s earlier wh– question (already discussed in 34). And (38) is again the coconut cream hoppers example we’ve seen twice already. This recycling suggests they don’t have enough genuinely distinct data to sustain the typology, so they keep dressing the same examples in new conceptual clothing.
-
Misuse of systemic concepts — In SFL, defaults are structural (e.g. interrogatives defaulting to “demand information”). Here, the “default purview” is not a systemic default but an analytic convenience. Calling it a “default” risks misleading readers into thinking the model is grounded in the grammar, when it is in fact grounded in their newly constructed grid.
More specifically:
Excerpt under review:
“For proposition or proposals that are open, often involving wh– questions, the default purview is pose (– speaker purview; + listener purview). … Though as example (30) above shows, open propositions can have their purview varied – in this case as aired, through I wonder.”
1. The illusion of a “default”
The authors claim that open wh– questions “default” to pose. But this “default” is only true by stipulation: they have defined pose as (– speaker purview; + listener purview), then observe that wh– interrogatives are typically structured as demands for information from the addressee. Rather than discovering something new, they are redescribing the already well-established systemic fact that interrogatives enact demands for information. The novelty of “purview” collapses into circular restatement.
2. Redundancy with SFL mood system
In Halliday & Matthiessen’s model, the correlation between mood type and speech function is already systemic:
-
interrogative ↔ demand for information
-
declarative ↔ statement of information
-
imperative ↔ demand for goods-&-services.
This account already captures Kristy’s wh– question in (37). To claim that “the default purview is pose” adds no explanatory depth; it simply repackages mood semantics into the “purview” grid, with no new descriptive reach.
3. Category slippage: proposition ↔ purview
The authors conflate two distinct dimensions:
-
proposition type: whether the clause is open (wh–) or closed (polar).
-
purview type: who is said to “own” or “share” responsibility for knowing.
They present the mapping as if the clause type “naturally” entails a purview, but in fact the “purview” category is artificially imposed. This slippage generates the illusion of systemic necessity where there is only analytic projection.
4. Reliance on recycled examples
The data presented are not fresh demonstrations but recycled:
-
Example (37) repeats Kristy’s wh– question from (34).
-
Example (38) repeats the “coconut cream hoppers” case already presented twice.
This recycling betrays the fragility of the framework. If the typology were descriptively robust, one would expect a rich array of distinct examples across Hasan’s corpus. Instead, the same handful of cases must be dressed up in different theoretical guises to sustain the typology.
5. Misuse of “default” as systemic category
In SFL, “default” is a technical concept tied to systemic probability: certain features are unmarked, carrying higher systemic probability in context. Here, “default purview” is neither probabilistic nor systemic; it is merely an analytic shorthand for “what their table already predicts.” By borrowing SFL’s terminology, the authors create an illusion of system-internal motivation that their model cannot supply.
Conclusion
This passage illustrates the fundamental weakness of the purview typology: it offers no explanatory insight beyond what mood semantics already covers, yet it recycles SFL’s terminology (“default”) and Hasan’s data to generate the appearance of theoretical novelty. The result is circular, redundant, and analytically fragile.
Sunday, 24 August 2025
Purview without System: Why ‘Share’ and ‘Air’ Misfire
Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 74):
These four options of assert, share, pose and air, offer resources for seeing how speakers nuance meanings in text and talk, so as to build affiliation and minimise the risk of a negative response. As Table 3.1 shows, they can be seen as arising from two variables, namely ± speaker purview and ± listener purview.
The table is presented as a two-variable system:
-
± speaker purview
-
± listener purview
This yields a four-cell typology: share, assert, pose, air.
At first glance, it looks neat. But there are two deep problems:
-
Category mistake in the dimensions themselves.
-
“Speaker purview” and “listener purview” are not interpersonal systems in Halliday’s sense. They are interpretations of stance and epistemic alignment—second-order construals of talk—rather than actual options available in the system network.
-
In other words: they treat what is negotiated in dialogue (who knows, who doesn’t) as if it were an input variable of the system. This is upside down: purview is construed in negotiation, not pre-given for system entry.
-
-
Misplaced systemics: projecting stance onto speech function.
-
The canonical SPEECH FUNCTION system already accounts for whether a speaker demands or gives information, and whether they do so congruently (declarative, interrogative) or metaphorically.
-
“Airing” and “sharing” are really evaluative stances realised by hedges, modal adjuncts, projection, or prosody—not distinct speech functions. To elevate them to the same systemic status as assert or pose is to flatten the delicate layering of semantics and conflate system with strategy.
-
Where the table breaks down
-
Assert and pose correspond roughly (if loosely) to canonical options in SFL: asserting propositions vs posing questions.
-
Share and air are parasitic: they depend entirely on construing stance toward knowledge (epistemic solidarity, hedged ignorance). These are better treated as resources of appraisal, modality, or projection.
So the table looks like a “system,” but it’s actually a hybrid of speech function and stance alignment, mixing strata and ranks. That’s why it appears plausible at first, but collapses under theoretical scrutiny.
A Square Peg Typology
When Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 74) finally formalise their four options in Table 3.1, the conceptual problem is exposed with striking clarity:
Listener purview | No listener purview | |
---|---|---|
Speaker purview | share | assert |
No speaker purview | pose | air |
On first glance, this looks like a neat systemic table. But an SFL reader will immediately see that “share” and “air” are not co-ordinates of the same order as “assert” and “pose.” They are not genuine options in a semantic system, but reformulations of stance or attitude toward participation.
The conflation is two-fold:
-
System and stance are treated as interchangeable. What belongs to the interpersonal system of SPEECH FUNCTION (assert/pose) is here combined with ways of orienting toward epistemic responsibility (share/air).
-
Dimensions of purview are mis-specified. “Speaker purview” is confused with the basic contrast of MOOD (declarative vs interrogative), while “listener purview” imports a participation effect that does not stratify with the system itself.
The table therefore produces a spurious typology. It suggests a system of four options where in fact two are categories and two are contextual glosses. The result is not a genuine systemic description but a square peg typology — forcing unlike phenomena into the same analytic frame.
What this shows is not the subtlety of affiliation, but the danger of confusing system with stance: once the orders of abstraction are collapsed, a table can be filled but theory is emptied.
Saturday, 23 August 2025
Why ‘Airing’ Collapses: Misreading Stance as Speech Function
Doran, Martin & Zappavigna (2025: 73-4):
Finally, it is possible to indicate that neither speaker or the listener is expected to know the answer to something – what we will call airing (– speaker purview; – listener purview). This often happens with the lexicalised phrase I don’t know (or perhaps more accurately – dunno). For example, once Kristy’s mother has finally managed to start getting Kristy dressed, Kristy asks her why her dress is only buttoned up on one side, to which her mother attempts to give an answer, before acknowledging that she simply doesn’t know.
In another conversation from Hasan’s data (AJ6B5), a mother is reading a cookbook with her daughter, and airs her exclamation about coconut cream hoppers through I wonder.
Importantly, it is still possible to give a response in these situations; but the position can be aired without indicating that anyone should be tied to it. This occurs in a separate conversation between mothers, when one mother is describing what it’s like when her child is in therapy for their disability. She suggests it might be her little break, but that she is not wedded to this at all.
ChatGPT Comments:
The authors here attempt to expand their taxonomy of “purview” with a final category they label airing, defined as (– speaker purview; – listener purview). This is supposed to cover cases where neither participant is expected to “know the answer,” typically expressed with “I don’t know” or “I wonder.”
This proposal falters at several points:
1. Taxonomy by residuals
-
The authors treat “airing” as the logical residual once speaker purview and listener purview have both been stripped away.
-
But this is an artefact of their grid-building, not of the semantics of exchange. It’s the familiar problem of “completing the square” — filling in a cell because the table demands it, not because the interactional phenomena actually call for it.
-
The examples themselves are heterogeneous: “I don’t know” is not parallel to “I wonder,” nor to “maybe it’s my little break.” These are different resources entirely, pressed into a single category for taxonomic neatness.
2. Misconstrual of “I don’t know”
-
In example (34), the mother says “and why they chose that side I don’t know.”
-
The authors gloss this as air/proposition.
-
But “I don’t know” is not a proposition about the world; it’s a modal assessment of the speaker’s knowledge state. In Halliday’s framework this belongs with modality, not with some new interpersonal role called “airing.”
-
Far from being a neutral “release of purview,” it strongly positions the mother as lacking epistemic authority, which itself is a meaning in negotiation (and can be strategic — deflecting, softening, protecting face).
-
To fold this into “purview” erases the modality system and creates a parallel interpersonal vocabulary that distorts what the language is doing.
3. Misconstrual of “I wonder”
-
In example (35), “I wonder what coconut cream hoppers are!” is glossed as air/proposition.
-
But “I wonder” is a mental process clause projecting an interrogative clause. It expresses a subjective stance (the mother’s curiosity), not an absence of speaker/listener purview.
-
To call this “airing” is to collapse clause type + projection into a pseudo-category invented for theoretical symmetry.
-
The move obscures the important difference between:
-
epistemic disclaimers (I don’t know),
-
affective stances (I wonder), and
-
tentative proposals (maybe it’s my little break).Each has its own grammar and interactional value; none is reducible to a missing purview box.
-
4. Category leakage
-
In (36), Renee says “I don’t know if that’s my little break.” This is glossed as air/proposition.
-
But this is a hypothetical with modal uncertainty (“I don’t know if …”), not parallel to the prior two cases.
-
Here, the “airing” label is stretched to cover any instance where the speaker softens commitment. That is precisely what the system of modality is for.
-
The fact that they need to sweep all these different structures under “airing” is a sign that the purview framework can’t actually handle epistemic disclaimers, stance markers, or hedging — all crucial to interpersonal meaning.
5. Theoretical redundancy
-
Everything in these examples is already systematically accounted for in SFL:
-
I don’t know → modal assessment of knowledge state.
-
I wonder … → projection of interrogative, expressing inclination/curiosity.
-
I don’t know if … → modalised proposal with epistemic hedging.
-
-
The “airing” category adds no explanatory power; it simply relabels these phenomena in terms of “purview,” a construct that duplicates and distorts the established systems of mood, modality, projection, and appraisal.
-
Worse, it collapses these systems into a single superficial box-ticking exercise.
6. Strategic mischaracterisation of dialogue
-
The claim that “airing” means “the position can be aired without indicating that anyone should be tied to it” is misleading.
-
In practice, these turns very much do tie meanings to the speaker: “I don’t know” positions the speaker as disclaiming knowledge; “I wonder” positions the speaker as inviting shared curiosity; “I don’t know if …” positions the speaker as hedging a claim.
-
The stance is not “untied” but highly interpersonal — signalling alignment, deference, or invitation.
-
By describing these as “– speaker purview; – listener purview,” the authors erase the interpersonal work that is actually happening.
Summary
The “airing” category exemplifies the residualist logic of this purview framework: filling in empty cells with whatever examples can be conscripted, regardless of whether they belong together. The result is a category collapse: epistemic disclaimers, stance markers, and hedged proposals are all swept under one heading, misrepresented as lacking purview.
From the standpoint of systemic functional linguistics, the work is already done by the existing resources of mood, modality, projection, and appraisal. “Airing” adds nothing — and in fact distorts the analysis by conflating distinct grammatical and semantic phenomena under a pseudo-category demanded by their matrix.
In other words…
The authors introduce a fourth category of “purview,” which they label airing, defined as (– speaker purview; – listener purview). This is supposed to capture utterances in which neither speaker nor listener is “expected to know” the answer. They exemplify with I don’t know and I wonder, treating these as structural indices of a distinct interpersonal move.
Several problems immediately arise.
-
Confusion of semantics with stance markers.The classification rests on idiomatic lexical items (dunno, I wonder) rather than on a principled analysis of speech function. These phrases are pragmatic markers signalling uncertainty or tentativeness. Treating them as evidence of a new kind of move confuses interpersonal meaning (commitment to a proposition) with the lexico-grammatical realisations that hedge such commitment. In systemic terms, “I don’t know” is an adjunct to mood, modulating the speaker’s orientation — not a separate speech function.
-
The incoherence of (– speaker purview; – listener purview).The proposed polarity is unstable. If the speaker genuinely disclaims purview and also withholds purview from the listener, then the exchange collapses: no one is positioned to take up the offer or demand. Communication requires some addressee alignment — even if minimal — otherwise the utterance would be unintelligible. In fact, in their own examples the listener is implicitly granted purview: Kristy may not know why the dress opens on one side, but she can still respond to her mother’s speculation or acknowledgment of ignorance. The category thus contradicts itself.
-
Retrofitting to Hasan’s data.The authors again misappropriate Hasan’s carefully analysed interactions. When a mother says I wonder what coconut cream hoppers are!, Hasan would treat this as a rhetorical demand for information (a question) or as a stance move inviting affiliation. Doran et al. relabel it “airing” but provide no systemic justification. They treat Hasan’s example as a mere illustration of their taxonomy, ignoring the rich theoretical grounding Hasan provided in the semantics of dialogue.
-
Mischaracterisation of responsibility.The authors claim that “airing” indicates “that no one should be tied to it.” But this is not true even in their data. In example (36), Renee says I don’t know if that’s my little break — here the speaker is very much tied to the utterance: it construes her subjective stance toward therapy routines. To say she is not wedded to it is an interpretive gloss, not an interpersonal function. The speaker retains responsibility for the construal, even if signalling tentativeness.
-
Category inflation.Rather than recognising that modalisation, hedging, and stance-taking are resources for modulating purview, the authors posit a wholly new category of “airing.” This multiplies terms unnecessarily, producing redundancy where systemic-functional theory already has robust means of accounting for uncertainty and subjectivity (e.g., modality, comment adjuncts, engagement resources in appraisal).
In sum: “Airing” is a mis-specified category built on shaky distinctions. It conflates stance markers with speech function, posits an incoherent (– purview; – purview) polarity, misreads Hasan’s data, and mistakes hedging for abdication of responsibility. The result is an inflated and unnecessary addition to the interpersonal system. Far from clarifying negotiation, it muddles the terrain and obscures the established systemic resources already at hand.